14 found
Order:
  1. Inference, Method and Decision.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (3):301-304.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  2. The justification of induction.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (4):527-539.
    We show there is only one consistent way to update a probability assignment, that given by Bayes's rule. The price of inconsistent updating is a loss of efficiency. The implications of this for the problem of induction are discussed.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  3.  72
    Bayesian confirmation: Paradise regained.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):467-476.
  4.  64
    Measuring truthlikeness.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1980 - Synthese 45 (3):463 - 487.
  5.  89
    Does the philosophy of induction rest on a mistake?R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (2):78-97.
  6.  27
    Probability magic unmasked.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1973 - Philosophy of Science 40 (2):227-233.
    It has been alleged that Bayesian usage of prior probabilities allows one to obtain empirical statements on the basis of no evidence whatever. We examine this charge with reference to several examples from the literature, arguing, first, that the difference between probabilities based on weighty evidence and those based on little evidence can be drawn in terms of the variance of a distribution. Moreover, qua summaries of vague prior knowledge, prior distributions only transmit the empirical information therein contained and, therefore, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7.  29
    Bayesian theory appraisal: A reply to Seidenfeld.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1979 - Theory and Decision 11 (4):441-451.
  8.  49
    The significance test controversy.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1973 - Synthese 26 (2):304 - 321.
    The pre-designationist, anti-inductivist and operationalist tenor of Neyman-Pearson theory give that theory an obvious affinity to several currently influential philosophies of science, most particularly, the Popperian. In fact, one might fairly regard Neyman-Pearson theory as the statistical embodiment of Popperian methodology. The difficulties raised in this paper have, then, wider purport, and should serve as something of a touchstone for those who would construct a theory of evidence adequate to statistics without recourse to the notion of inductive probability.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  1
    Distributive justice.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1978 - In A. Hooker, J. J. Leach & E. F. McClennen (eds.), Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory. D. Reidel. pp. 91--119.
  10.  28
    Probabilistic Confirmation Theory and the Goodman Paradox.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1973 - American Philosophical Quarterly 10 (2):157 - 162.
  11.  50
    Support.R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1977 - Synthese 36 (2):181 - 193.
  12.  46
    The Work of E. T. Jaynes on Probability, Statistics and Statistical Physics. [REVIEW]E. T. Jaynes & R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (2):193-210.
    An important contribution to the foundations of probability theory, statistics and statistical physics has been made by E. T. Jaynes. The recent publication of his collected works provides an appropriate opportunity to attempt an assessment of this contribution.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  13.  18
    Isaac Levi. For the sake of the argument. Ramsey test conditionals, inductive inference, and nonmonotonic reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York, and Oakleigh, Victoria, 1996, xv + 341 pp. [REVIEW]R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (3):1041-1043.
  14.  7
    Review: Isaac Levi, For the Sake of the Argument. Ramsey Test Conditionals, Inductive Inference, and Nonmonotic Reasoning. [REVIEW]R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (3):1041-1043.